Ausgabe 1, Band 4 – Mai 2008
The Judge as Tragic Hero: An Arendtian Critique of Judging
Roger Berkowitz
Academic Director, Hannah Arendt Center for Politics and Humanities at Bard College NY
I.
The competing moral imperatives in the fugitive slave cases were clear to the judges Cover describes. On one side was their belief that slavery was evil, and that it contravened both natural law and common morality. On the other side was their argument that they were rule-bound actors who were obliged to enforce the democratically enacted Fugitive Slave Act. These positions appeal to two different understandings of the verb and the action, to judge. The first appeals to judgment, understood in the Kantian sense, as a free act of autonomous yet universal legislation. The second appeals to the judges’ understanding of themselves as role-players who are bonded to the application of particular cases to general legal rules.
In exploring Arendt’s unwillingness to resolve the paradox of autonomy and limitation, I read Arendt’s own act of judging in the epilogue of her book Eichmann in Jerusalem as an ethical critique of the Israeli judges who, in sentencing Eichmann to death, justified their decision by appealing to their role as interpreters of general laws. In appealing to laws and legal precedents, the positive legal system, which, Arendt argues, was completely inadequate to justify the court’s decision, the Israeli court, like the ante-bellum judges in Cover’s study, sought to deny their autonomy in a case in which ethical acceptance of their at least partial autonomy was called for. Rather than meet the unique and exceptional case presented by Eichmann in its terrifying particularity, the Israeli judges subsumed Eichmann’s compliance with a genocidal regime under the existing criminal laws of Israel. By opposing her confident and definitive judgment as an appeal to the normative community to the judges’ rule-bound approach, Arendt suggests that judges, at least in certain extraordinary circumstances, should recognize their freedom to judge freed from the constraints of general guidelines and autonomously will themselves to act. Arendt appeals to all of us, judges as well as those of us who may seek to maintain our innocence by faithfully obeying the law, to assume our obligation to think, to judge, and to act in response to particular events without the illusory assurance of the judicial ‘can’t.’ Such an attitude toward the law need not deny the importance of law as a stabilizing and moral force in society; it does, however, suggest that obedience to law should proceed under the aegis of a law that acknowledges transformative potentialities, rather than operate under the fiction of legal certainty.
II. Thoughtlessness
The problem of the banality of evil reaches its height when the duty to obey the laws can be invoked in the name of evil. Because obedience to the law remains for many a cardinal virtue—even greater than the simple virtue of obedience to orders,—we need not think about what we are doing when we obey laws. Like wardens and executioners, businessmen whose lawyers tell them that it is not illegal to build dangerously defective cars or to pollute the world’s environment, do not usually call up their local constitutional scholars or moral philosophers to discuss the implications of their acts. While reflection and argumentation may (or may not) suggest that executing a murderer is different from exterminating entire races of people, the agents of the legal system, like Eichmann , rely on legal authorization of their actions to justify their violence. It is easier for an executioner, instead of thinking about the death penalty in general or its specific application to the prisoner before him, simply to throw the switch and consider himself as a law abiding citizen. Indeed such rationalizations are necessary for the efficient workings of our modern society.
III. Autonomy and Limitation
Those who fault Arendt for not specifying the normative presuppositions of politics may miss the democratic spirit in which Arendt’s paradoxical presentation of politics is rooted. Politics seeks to erect boundaries that limit freedom in order of protecting a legal order; yet, in a democracy, there cannot be any extra-societal limits on the boundless capacity of action to be self-creating and thus simultaneously world-destroying. That is, in a democratic society, the only limits that can be relied on to restrain the boundlessness of action are self-imposed limits, which are often no limits at all. That is why Arendt rightly saw that in a democracy hubris and moderation are respectively the most subversive and most virtuous of political temptations. Hubris is what destroys democratic polities because it extends the truth of democratic autonomy to unsustainable limits. As Cornelius Castoriadis argues:
If the unlimited autonomy of hubris elevates Man to God, moderation, on the other hand, is the virtue of democratic politics because it recognizes that autonomy can only be preserved if it is limited. Democracy is the regime of self-limitation; once formed, the first goal of democracies is to bring about the institutionalization of self-restraint.
IV. Constitutionalism and Judging
How exactly a judge might negotiate the paradox of judging, Arendt never fully elaborates; however, in the epilogue of Eichmann in Jerusalem, she publicly announces a hypothetical judgment, which she imagines should have been the decision issued by the court. In the final section, I read Arendt’s judgment of Eichmann as a guide to how ‘we,’ as judges with the responsibility to speak the truth of the Constitution even as we deny the certainty of that truth, should negotiate the paradox of judgment. The judge, Arendt argues, must act--at least in certain situations--to re-authorize the existing framework of legal limitations.
V. Judging Eichmann
Near the end of Eichmann in Jerusalem, Arendt quotes from the District Court of Jerusalem’s opinion in which it found Adolf Eichmann guilty of crimes against the Jewish people:
The issue of responsibility looms large in the Eichmann trial and in the Court’s opinion. Eichmann claimed that he could not be held personally responsible for crimes committed by a mass of people. He claimed that he was merely a cog in a machine, and that his role in carrying out the Final Solution was an historical accident, that almost any other German could have (and would have, given the opportunity) taken his place if he had refused. Eichmann claimed, in essence, that when all are guilty, none is responsible.
The judges’ insistence that Eichmann’s responsibility inhered in his intention to break the law represents an absolute blindness to the very danger that Eichmann embodies. It represents, Arendt suggests, a resistance to thinking, a self-certain and banal thoughtlessness which Arendt argues should be understood as a resistance to the perspective of the other. This resistance to thinking is precisely what Arendt condemns in Eichmann:
That most reliable of safeguards is none other than the certainty of one’s own convictions and identity. Eichmann’s thoughtlessness is revealed to Arendt in his self-certainty. Even during his trial, Eichmann maintained that he had acted according to his conscientious duty as a law-abiding citizen. It is for this reason that Arendt cannot sanction the Israeli judge’s attempt to kill Eichmann with no other justification than that the law of the victor authorizes it. The Court’s blindness to Eichmann’s reality—the reality of his certainty of moral conviction as having acted according to his duty to obey the law—is the flip side of its unshakable faith in its own reality—the reality of the judges’ own certainty of their moral obligation to judge Eichmann according to Israeli law.
The moral actor, like Eichmann, expects his confession of the non-universality of his conscientious action to be met with a similar confession, a reciprocal acknowledgment of the evil and self-certainty of his judges; instead, the moral actor meets with the ‘hard heart’ of judging consciousness which “rejects any continuity with the other” and repulses and expels that other as evil in contrast to the serene beauty of the judging consciousness. The Israeli judges, like Hegelian ‘beautiful souls,’ retreat into their comfortable hierarchies (comfortable because they are hierarchical) that enable them to judge Eichmann precisely for what Eichmann admits to doing which is participating in the holocaust.
I will come to Arendt’s actual judgment in which she hangs a millstone from Eichmann’s neck shortly, but it is first necessary to understand how Arendt justifies her ability to sit in judgment of Eichmann. Arendt’s attempt to understand Eichmann as worthy of respect, threatens to eliminate the space, the spectatorial distance as well as the temporal reflection which makes judging possible. Judging requires standards and criteria that are applied to another; but when that other is understood, and understood as reciprocal actors to those who judge, judging that other becomes in a sense judging oneself. How is it that Arendt’s injunction to think so as to hear the words of the other does not lead to situation in which judging is impossible?
Does this mean therefore that Arendt, forced to decide between autonomy and limitation, resolves the paradox of judging firmly on the side of autonomy? And if she does, how is her autonomous judgment to be justified except as the prerogative of the victor? Let me state unequivocally that I think there is a difference—one more meaningful than the fact that Arendt and the Israeli judges represent the victors and Eichmann the losers—between the judgments made by Eichmann and the one made by his judges. That difference, however, is hidden within the legalistic justifications of the Israeli court’s opinion and only made explicit by Arendt’s claim for the intersubjectivity of her judgment.
Arendt announces what she says is the sentence the court should have read, but dared not. Against Eichmann’s protests that he “had never been a Jew-hater,” and that he was a ‘victim’ being forced to ‘suffer for the acts of others,’ Arendt imagines the court responding:
What is necessary in a bureaucratic and violent world such as ours, Arendt suggests, is the maturity to take responsibility for objective consequences of one’s actions, regardless of one’s subjective intent. Importantly, her speech is an argument; it does not seek authority in the laws, but primarily serves to justify her judgment that Eichmann must be held responsible for crimes he committed, even though he lacked, in legal terms, the requisite mens rea or responsibility. The difference between Arendt’s judgment and the decision read by the Israeli Court centers around Arendt’s decision to employ forcefully the rhetorical device of the first person plural: ‘We.’ It is her use of “we,” and thus her attempt to speak to and for an imagined world community, a community that she transforms even as she attempts to speak for it, that, I argue, is the key to Arendt’s attempt to negotiate the paradox of autonomy and limitation.
“We find,” says Arendt. First, therefore, Arendt seeks to assume collective responsibility for the decision to hang Eichmann. She proclaims her decision as an at least partially autonomous—as opposed to a fully limited—judgment. Second, by using the collective ‘we,’ Arendt presumes to speak for the relevant community. “We,” she argues, find that “no member of the human race” should have to share the Earth with Eichmann. Arendt turns the trial of Eichmann into a collective accusation rather than an attempt to prove specific guilty acts or a guilty mind. She thus professes a faith that the human community will agree with her assertion. By invoking the collective ‘we,’ Arendt asks those for whom she speaks to accept her characterization of themselves, to accept and take responsibility for their collective action, and thus in doing so, to re-constitute ourselves as individuals.
In writing ‘we find,’ Arendt imaginatively traverses what I have argued is the central paradox of her political and philosophical thinking, the paradox between political autonomy and political limitation. In sentencing Eichmann based on a subjective determination—the ‘we find’—Arendt acknowledges that she, and through her the human race, is the source of the norms upon which collective judgment is founded. In terms of Arendt’s own vocabulary, speaking the sentence becomes a political action through which she injects her own self—and with her the human race—into the public sphere of narrative self-creation. Who Hannah Arendt is and, more importantly, who the world is cannot but change as the public begins the never-ending process of interpreting and re-interpreting the implications of their collective statement. Arendt’s speech is, in essence, a claim about collective identity; as a thoughtful claim, it is one that does not reassert a pre-existing and unchanging identity. As a claim, however, it is one that she, nor nobody else can control. By saying ‘we’ instead of saying ‘I’, Arendt transforms a legal sentence of positive assertion, ‘Based on the law and the precedent I find ...’ into a political appeal to a collective identity which can either be accepted or rejected.
When Arendt says “We find,” I believe that she employs the first person plural ‘we’ as an appeal to the human community; she addresses that community and appeals to it to accept and understand her judgment; in doing so, she provides an example of one way to negotiate the political paradox of autonomy and limitation and the judicial paradox of legislating and following. Negotiation of the paradox requires the confidence to judge and to speak for others, but also the humility to present oneself as a conduit for the voice of a larger group. Further, to negotiate the paradox one must show the courage to announce her decision as an appeal for support rather than as a conclusion of law.
Judges must recognize that their authority does come from their limited role as interpreters; without this, stability is destined to remain an illusive goal. Yet Arendt’s judgment in the epilogue demonstrates that there are times, certain occasions, when judging should cease to be a routine of deference and technique, and instead must rise to the level of autonomy and natality. Judges, as political actors, have a responsibility to make claims on the identity of the polity they are authorized to speak for. That identity, Arendt argues, is never given as unalterable; instead, it must be sought and attained through action. Judges, as actors who in their arguments, indictments, and sentences speak for the community in the first person plural ‘we,’ have the responsibility to reveal our world as it is. It is for us who are not (officially) judges, therefore, to respond.
VI. Conclusion
The ante-bellum judges who upheld the Fugitive Slave Act, consciously or not, refused to confront the dilemma revealed by the absence of ultimate judicial standards and avoided the responsibility to judge that the freedom of interpretation demands. As a consequence, they had little difficulty determining a stable space from which to judge the constitutionality of slavery and of the Act. They refused to risk their stable conception of themselves as neutral legal minds; instead they presented themselves as tragic heroes. In the higher interest of their legal roles and the interests of society, they were willing, even eager, to sacrifice concerns of justice to what they thought were the requirements of the law. They appealed to a vision of themselves as bonded to the law, a vision that made their own job easier and also resonated with the popular image of judges as those who apply rather than make the laws.
It is the spectatorial distance which is necessary in order to judge another and yet doubly denied in the Eichmann trial. First, because Eichmann acted conscientiously and according to his duty, the attempt to push him away as different, as evil, as Other failed. Second, because Eichmann’s crimes were so extraordinary, the effort to bring their judgment under the rubric of legal positivism approximated legal sophistry. Arendt does not reject the ideals of that vision of judging appealed to by the ante-bellum and Israeli judges. On the contrary, she recognizes that a significant part of being a judge is to understand oneself as limited and as stable. Yet, Arendt, like Cover, insists that following rules does not exhaust the activity of judging.
She appeals to the judge as someone who must have the security of identity to risk that identity; especially when confronted with situations which reveal the hidden assumptions of that identity, a judge must be willing to understand those whom she judges as well as herself. But a judge must not only seek to understand; the judge must also accept her position as an autonomous actress who has the freedom and responsibility to speak for the community in a way that both affirms and changes what the community is and what it will become. Judges rhetorically represent and speak for polities; Arendt and Cover insist that when they do, they take care to neither treat the identity of the polity as certain and unchanging, nor to ignore the fact that their authority to speak for the community derives from the consent of the community. In short, judges can neither be wholly autonomous nor absolutely limited. Rather, they must be both; they must also be neither.
An earlier version of this article was published in: The Graduate Review, v. 1, #1 Spring 1994, continued as, Critical Sense (Berkeley).
The author would like to thank Jennifer Culbert, Jesse Goldhammer, Hannah Pitkin, Ellen Rigsby, Austin Sarat, Tom Scanlon, and Jeremy Waldron, each of whom read and generously commented on various drafts of this paper.
Notes
1 Robert Cover, Justice Accused, (1975).
2 The Act dealt primarily with the jurisdiction and appointment of federal magistrates who would issue certificates for the return of escaped slaves. The magistrate was to oversee the proceedings and examine the affidavits of the slaveholder or his representative and then issue a certificate for the slave’s return. Slaves themselves were explicitly prevented from testifying and the Act also compensated the magistrates $10 when they returned slaves and only $5 when they denied the slaveholder’s petition. Id., pg. 175.
3 See Article 4, US. Constitution.
4 See Cover, supra note 1, at 119-97.
5 Id. at 119.
6 Id. at 120 citing Jackson v. Bullock, 12 Conn. 39 (1837) (Judge Bissell dissenting). See also Justice McLean’s statement in Miller v. McQuerry that the question of the natural right of slavery “is a field which judges can not explore” (cited in Id. at 120).
7 For an interesting theory on why judges appear to welcome their subjection to law, see Slavoj Zizek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (1989). Zizek argues that the law of the law as it is expressed from Kant onwards, is that we must deny ourselves the free reign of our inclinations. The moral law, therefore, is precisely the renunciation of the desire to transgress the limits of the law—i.e. to subject oneself to the law. According to Zizek, what we in fact desire is the law itself.
8 The tragic flaw that compels the ante-bellum judges to uphold laws they consider inherently unjust is the supposed virtue of fidelity to the law. Like Captain Vere in Melville’s novel Billy Budd and Creon in Sophocles Antigone, the ante-bellum judges appeal to their role as agents of the legal order to justify actions which are, in the objective nomos in which the judges exist, considered unjust.
9 See Robert Cover, “Violence and the Word” 95 Yale Law Review 1601 (1986).
10 See Jerry Frug, “Argument As Character,” 40 Stanford Law Review 869 (1988).
11The judges’ rhetorical move of presenting her role as that of merely interpreting the will of the people serves as a legitimizing discourse. Id., at 869.
12 Cover advances a number of legal and constitutional theories available to the judges and advanced by the lawyers representing the slaves which could have been adopted by the judges. See Cover, supra note 1, at 62-119 and 131-197.
13 Id.
14 See e.g. Hannah Arendt, “‘Eichmann in Jerusalem:’ An Exchange of Letters between Gershom Scholem and Hannah Arendt,” in Jew as Pariah, ed. by Ron H. Feldman (1978) pg. 248-9.
15 In reading Arendt as ethically clearing a space in which politics and judgment is held to be both necessary and impossible, I am suggesting a connection between Arendt and what certain contemporary philosophers have called ethical deconstruction. See e.g. Drucilla Cornell, The Philosophy of the Limit, (1992) pgs. 81-90 and Jacques Derrida, “The Force of Law,” 11 Cardozo Law Review 919 (1990). Ethical deconstruction, as developed by Jacques Derrida and Drucilla Cornell relies on what they call a double move in reading through which the reader must both be responsive to what is being read, and also take responsibility for what the reader makes the text become as a result of his reading. Translated into the sphere of ethics, the subject must recognize that the Other she confronts exists as other and can never be known. No matter how one tries to bring the Other into oneself, the Other as Other always resists such a sublimation and maintains itself as Other through its excess—its joussiance— which cannot be unmediately represented. The Other therefore imposes certain limitations on an ethical subject’s attempt to know, to understand, or to read the Other. An ethical reading is one in which the reader is understood to exercise responsibility to the otherness of the text, a self-imposed limit to the reader’s claim of autonomy which respects the integrity of the other. Likewise, ethical judgment requires that the judge take seriously the particularity of the person be judged and refrain from unproblematically subsuming particular persons and events under general rules. For a more detailed analysis of ethical deconstruction in Cornell’s philosophy, see my review of Cornell’s work, “Risk of the Self: Drucilla Cornell’s Transformative Philosophy,” 9 Berkeley Women’s Law Journal 175 (1994).
16 Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem (1963) at 252 [hereafter Eichmann].
17 Arendt notes that Eichmann had never read Mein Kampf (Id. at 33) and professed to have Jewish friends and family which he presents as proof that he had no ill will toward Jews (Id. at 29-30).
18 Id. 276
19 Arendt argues that Eichmann understood himself and reality only through ‘officialese,’ what he called his only language. Officialese, the language of clichés and empty talk proved to be “the most reliable of all safeguards against the words and the presence of others, and hence against reality as such.” Id. at 49.
20 Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition, (1958) pg. 5 [hereafter HC].
21Eichmann, supra note 16, at 33. In his search for security and prestige, Eichmann is similar to what Arendt terms the pater familias, the family man. [Hannah Arendt, “Organized Guilt and Universal Responsibility,” in Arendt, The Jew as Pariah, supra note 14, at 232.] In her early attempts to understand why so many ‘normal’ Germans participated in the Nazi genocide machine, Arendt suggests that the ‘chaotic economic conditions of our time’ have uprooted families and elevated a concern for security to the forefront of the bourgeoisie mind. For the sake of his economic security and his family, the bourgeoisie family man, Arendt argues, “was ready to sacrifice his beliefs, his honor, and his human dignity ... The only condition he put was that he should be fully exempted from responsibility for his acts.” Id.
22 Id.
23 Id. at 234. Arendt quotes a dialogue between an American correspondent and a German soldier:
Q: Did you kill people in the Camp? A: Yes.
Q: Did you poison them with gas? A: Yes.
...
Q: What did you think of what was going on? A: It was bad at first but we got used to it.
Q: Do you know the Russians will hang you? A: (Bursting into tears) Why should they? What have I done? [Id. pg. 231, (quoting PM, Sunday, Nov. 12, 1944)].
As Arendt remarks, “Really he had done nothing. He had only carried out orders and since when has it been a crime to carry out orders?” at 231.
24 George Kateb, Hannah Arendt, (1984) pg. 76 citing Hannah Arendt, “Personal Responsibility Under Dictatorship.”
25 Cover, “Violence and the Word,” supra note 9, at 1613.
26 Id. 1625.
27 Id., at 1613-1615.
28 Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 16, at 24. This of course is a controversial claim in legal theory debates. See H.L.A. Hart, “Legal Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” 71 Harvard Law Review, 598 (1958).
29 Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 16, at 147.
30 “For the sad and very uncomfortable truth of the matter probably was that it was not his fanaticism but his very conscience that prompted Eichmann to adopt his uncompromising attitude during the last year of the war, as it had prompted him to move in the opposite direction for a short time three years before.” Id., at 146.
31 Id. at 135-36. It is interesting to note that Hegel warned of the danger of Kant’s being read in this subjectivist way in the Preface to the Philosophy of Right. See Hegel, The Philosophy of Right, trans. by T.M. Knox (1952) pgs. 5-6. For an argument that Hegel’s attack on J.F. Fries and the nationalistic, ant-Semitic, and terrorist student movement which Fries supported is presented as a warning against the degeneration of Kantian philosophy into an “ethic of mere subjective intentions,” see “The Owl of Minerva and the Critical Mind,” by Shlomo Avineri, in Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State, ed. by Avineri (1972), pg. 120.
32 While Arendt recognized that outright resistance to totalitarian regimes is sometimes impossible, she does argue that even if one does not resist, he has the power to ‘do nothing’ (Arendt, Jew as Pariah, supra note 14, at 248). Even members of the SS, Arendt notes, could ask to be relieved of their duties without any penalties. (249) For another account of how individual people within post-totalitarian or bureaucratic regimes can exercise power simply by asserting their right to not participate in the regime’s programs, see Vaclav Havel, “The Power of the Powerless,” trans. by P. Wilson, in Vaclav Havel, Living in Truth, ed. by Jan Vladislav, 1986.
33 Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 16, at 136.
34 See Martin Heidegger, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, (1984) pg. 138. The characteristic of thrownness (Geworfenheit) is a metaphysical presupposition of our being in, and therefore, to a certain degree, overwhelmed by and governed by, our world.
35 For a more involved account of these dilemmas see Cornelius Castoriadis, “The Greek Polis and the Creation of Democracy,” in Cornelius Castoriadis, Philosophy, Politics, and Autonomy (1991), pg. 81 [hereafter Castoriadis].
36 Arendt usually speaks of freedom and not autonomy and she has significant reasons for doing so. Because action is always narrative, and thus indeterminate, man can, as she says, never master his world. [Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 234] Autonomy, understood as self-rule, is in many ways closer to sovereignty which Arendt recognizes as an impossible but necessary aspiration. Yet Arendt’s use of freedom is often very similar to what I mean by autonomy. Freedom, she says, “is the freedom to call something into being which did not exist before, which was not given, not even as an object of cognition or imagination, and which therefore, strictly speaking, could not be known.” [Hannah Arendt, “What is Freedom?,” in Between Past and Future, ed. by Hannah Arendt (1977) pg. 151 {hereafter Freedom}] Thus freedom includes the ability to create, even if such creation is ultimately indeterminate and contingent. Understood in this way, freedom and autonomy are synonymous. I favor autonomy because I think it better represents the thrust of Arendt’s meaning, even though I recognize that in doing so I risk the implication of sovereignty which is unintended.
37 See Seyla Benhabib, “Judgment and the Moral Foundations of Politics in Arendt’s Thought,” Political Theory (Feb. 1988) pg. 32 [hereafter Judgment].
38 Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 175.
39 Id., at 176.
40 Id., at 178.
41Id., at 181, 183.
42 See Id., at 230-36.
43 Id., at 198.
44 Id., at 199.
45 Feminist critics of Arendt have argued that Arendt’s positioning of the pre-political realm as prior to politics is tied to her privileging of praxis over poesis and thus the male public realm over the female private realm. While I agree that Arendt’s schematic distinction between the public and the private realms in The Human Condition is susceptible to such a critique, I believe that Arendt’s refusal to ever freeze the political and her embrace of a temporal politics of both limitation and autonomy disrupts any interpretations of her work that too heavily emphasize her schematic division of the world.
46 Hannah Arendt, “Civil Disobedience,” in Hannah Arendt, The Crises of the Republic (1972) pg. 79 .
47 Arendt, HC, supra, note 20, at 191.
48 But Arendt’s public space cannot simply be the formal legal guarantees of free speech and the right of assembly. Rather, it is the place of critical reflection, courage, responsibility, and the creation of new norms and orders. Lacking these substantive elements, Arendt’s public space becomes “just an open space for advertising, mystification, and pornography—as is increasingly the case today.” Castoriadis, supra note 35, at 113. For a fascinating conception of what public space requires (access to a symbolic universe), see Drucilla Cornell, Transformations (1993) pgs. 57-111.
49 See Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self (1992) pg. 103 , and Judgment, supra note 37. Benhabib argues, through Habermas, that Arendt neglects the need for a moral foundation of judgment.
50 Alan Keenan, “Arendtian Themes in the Work of Ernesto Laclau,” paper on file with author.
51 Arendt, Human Condition, supra note 20, at 205.
52 Arendt, Freedom, supra note 36, at 146.
53 See Arendt’s discussion of Jefferson’s and Paine’s conclusion that it was “‘vanity and presumption [to govern] beyond the grave’” in Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (1963) pg. 233.
54 Castoriadis, supra note 35, at 115.
55 Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 243.
56Id., at 247. See also On Revolution, supra note 53, at 175: “There is an element of the world-building capacity of man in the human faculty of making and keeping promises.”
57Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 246.
58 Id. 245.
59 Castoriadis, supra note 35, at 115.
60 Id.
61 See Robert Cover, “Nomos and Narrative,” 97 Harvard Law Review 4 (1983).
62 Arendt, On Revolution, supra note 53, at 183-4 (Quoting Rousseau).
63 Id., 183-4.
64Arendt, On Revolution, supra note 53, at 239.
65Id., at 198-99.
66 Id., at 200-202. pg. 201.
67 Id., at 192.
68 Id., at 198.
69 Id., at 204.
70 Id., at 239.
71 This is, of course, precisely the argument of many liberal theorists in favor of constitutional government. For example, Bruce Ackerman argues that the meaning of constitutional government is that there are certain foundational issues, such as free speech, equal protection, etc. which are too contentious to be openly debated in the public sphere. Ackerman, “Why Dialogue?,” 86 J. of Philosophy 16-17 (Jan. 1989) (cited in Benhabib, Situating the Self, supra note 49, at 96-97). Seyla Benhabib makes a similar argument but argues that free speech, as the most important norm, should be the only one off limits of debate, a contradiction which she is comfortable with as the substantive normative standard for politics. See Benhabib, Situating the Self, supra note 49, at 99. Arendt too believed that substantive limits on autonomy were necessary. [See her letter to Karl Jaspers complaining that during the McCarthy trials: “the judiciary branch … has ceased to function and ... everything hinges now on the opinion of the people.. … The republic, which should define the framework and the limits of democracy, is being dissolved from within by democracy.” (Arendt to Jaspers, December 21, 1953, In Correspondence: Hannah Arendt, Karl Jaspers, (1993) pg. 235).] The difference between Arendt and the liberals is not that one thinks substantive limits on autonomy are necessary and the other does not, but that while Benhabib believes it ethically necessary to name the limit, Arendt argues that naming the limit is precisely what is unethical.
72 Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 233, 244, (my italics).
73 Arendt expresses what may be her utopian vision of permanent politics in describing a letter Jefferson wrote to John Adams. “And Jefferson’s true notion of happiness comes out very clearly. .. when he lets himself go in a mood of playful and sovereign irony and concludes one of his letters to Adams as follows: ‘May we meet there again, in Congress, with our ancient Colleagues, and receive with them the seal of approbation ‘Well done, good and faithful servants.’ Here, behind the irony, we have the candid admission that life in Congress, the joys of discourse, of legislation, of transacting business, of persuading and being persuaded, were to Jefferson no less conclusively a foretaste of an eternal bliss to come than the delight of contemplation had been for medieval piety.” Id., pg 131 (citing Jefferson’s letter to Adams of 11 April 1823).
74 McCullogh v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316, 407 (1819). Arendt quotes a version of this issued by Woodrow Wilson: “[T]he Supreme Court is indeed, in Woodrow Wilson’s phrase, ‘a kind of Constitutional Assembly in continuous session’.” Arendt, On Revolution, supra note 53, at 200.
75Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 16, at 247 (first italics added).
76 Id., at 278.
77 Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 245.
78 See Sanford Kadish, “Mens Rea—The Mental State Accompanying The Forbidden Acts,” in Criminal Law and its Process (1962) ed. by Paulsen and Kadish, pgs. 229-270. Every crime has a specific level of mens rea which a person must be found to have before he can be convicted. In certain circumstances, such as insanity or duress, persons who committed a crime which they intended to commit, may not be considered responsible—and thus would not be considered guilty—if they are not found to have the sufficient level of guilt.
79 Eichmann, supra note 16, at 150, 105.
80 A mistake of law (claiming that one did an act but did not know it was against the law) is no defense in criminal law. Yet one cannot be prosecuted for committing a wrong, even an intended wrong, if the wrong is not illegal.
81 Cover, “Violence and the Word,” supra note 9, at 1609.
82 Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind, (1978) pg. 49.
83 Id., at 263.
84 Life of the Mind, 5.
85 For an example of the difficulty of imagining oneself through the eyes of the other and in doing so of putting the very identity of one’s self at risk, see Drucilla Cornell’s essay “Diastrologies,” in Cornell, Transformations, supra note 48, at 45-56, 170-94.
86 For an explanation of what I mean by ‘risk of the self,’ see my article, “Risk of the self: Drucilla Cornell’s Transformative Philosophy,” 9 Berkeley Women’s Law Journal, 175 (1994).
87 Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 243.
88 Id. at 241.
89 Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. by A.V. Miller, at 388.
90 Id. 392.
91 Id. 404.
92 Id.
93 Eichmann, supra note 20 at 53.
94 Id. at 54.
95 Hegel, at 405.
96 Arendt, HC, supra note 20, at 241.
97 Id. at 241.
98 Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 16, at 274.
99 Id., at 253-54. Arendt makes similar arguments in her essay “Civil Disobedience,” in which she argues that the authority of judges is dependent upon the consent of the people, a consent which is contingent on the judges’ commitment to operate within a defined and limited legal sphere. See Arendt, “Civil Disobedience,” supra note 46, at 99-102.
100 Arendt, “Civil Disobedience,” supra note 46, at 99.
101 Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 16, at 279. (emphasis my own).
102 Herbert Spiegelberg, “On the Right to Say ‘We’: A linguistic and Phenomenological Analysis,” in George Psathas, ed., Phenomenological Sociology (1973) 129, 133.
103 Id., at 130.
104 Id. 136-7.
105 Id. The right to say “we” assumes an “‘arrogance of power’ behind the patronizing usurpation of the right to speak for the ‘free’ people of the world, when they have never been asked, or the arrogant claim to speak for the ‘old’ or the ‘new’ generation ...” Id., at 130. In defending a limited right to say “we,” Psathas argues that the frequent misuse of “we” as a persuasive device designed to silence others who may have disagreed, must be replaced by an invitation to disagree and catch the speaker in a lie. Though we will continue to employ the third person plural and presume to speak for absent others, we also invite critics to show up our arrogance.